THBT: On balance, abortion is immoral [for @Bones]
The participant that receives the most points from the voters is declared a winner.
Voting will end in:
- Publication date
- Last updated date
- Type
- Rated
- Number of rounds
- 3
- Time for argument
- One week
- Max argument characters
- 15,000
- Voting period
- Two weeks
- Point system
- Multiple criterions
- Voting system
- Open
- Minimal rating
- 1,761
RESOLUTION:
THBT: On balance, abortion is immoral.
BURDEN OF PROOF:
BoP is shared equally. Pro argues that abortion is morally wrong. Con argues that abortion is morally permissible.
DEFINITIONS:
Abortion is “the willful and direct termination of a human pregnancy and of the developing offspring.”
Immoral means “morally wrong.”
On balance means “under usual circumstances.”
RULES:
1. All specifications presented in the description are binding to both participants.
2. Only Bones may accept.
- Direct harm: This action has a direct adverse effect on some other person.
- Neglecting a moral duty: Someone ought to do something (like follow an agreed-on contract) but fails to do so.
- An infant born in a coma with no past conscious experiences is a person, and killing them is wrong.
- Newborns are dependent on their parents and on society, but killing them is wrong.
- Killing a child is as bad as killing an adult, if not worse. Thus, it is clear that the potential to live a long life is morally significant, while a human’s level of biological development is not.
- Missed opportunities (reduction in life years): The comatose individual could have lived a long life
- Lack of choice: No choice was given to the comatose individual
- Violation of a social contract: We would not want someone to kill us or steal our opportunities, so it would be wrong to do so to someone else
- P1: Removing an unborn child’s potential conscious experiences is harmful.
- P2: Abortion is removing an unborn child’s potential conscious experiences.
- C1: Therefore, abortion is harmful.
- P1: Removing bodily support after making someone dependent on oneself is a direct harm.
- P2: Abortion is removing bodily support after making someone dependent on oneself.
- C1: Abortion is a direct harm
- P1: A child’s right to live outweighed their parent’s right not to raise them in ancient times.
- P2: Pregnancy in modern times is less inconvenient than raising a child in ancient times.
- C1: A child’s right to live outweighs their mother’s right to avoid pregnancy in modern times.
- The argument I will be defending takes the following form.
- I suspect there won’t be much debate here as it is trivial that something is wrong if it violates a moral entitlement or it has morally unacceptable consequences, and that if abortion is wrong, it would be for one of these two reasons.
- There are several reasons to believe that entities are persons if and only if they have (i) actualizable interests (ii) or their interests can be indexed to some prior mental state. Minimally, an entity is a person if at one point they have experienced non-trivial sentience. Here, I use non-trivial to convey the primitive difference between a fly’s sentience and a human being's sentience, only the latter of which can be said to be non-trivial. Formally,
- (∀xPx ↔ Nx ∨ Cx) For all x, x is a person if and only if they have interests N at time t or N is in E’s interest at t and B is capable of having an interest in N at t
- Px: x is a person
- Nx: x has an interest N at t
- Cx: x N is in E’s interest at t and B is capable of having an interest in N at t
- Here, I take Korz's (2002) notion of capable, where for E to be capable of having an interest in object O requires that at time t - n (prior to t) through t, E has certain beliefs and desires, and were certain logically possible events to have occurred after t - n but prior to t, E would have desired O at t.
- Because the above can be cumbersome to repeat, it can be simplified for future reference as
- P↔Q
- P: a person
- Q: Nx ∨ Cx (refer to above)
- There is immense explanatory power in favour of this theory of personhood.
- General abductive motivations
- Abduction refers to a type of inference which looks at our domain of knowledge and defers to the best available explanation. It can be said that this theory is abductively virtuous.
- Just look around and you will see that any entity who you think is a person (your parents, yourself, people from five thousand years ago) are people who meet the proposed disjunct. If the person you picked is a person, then they are non-trivially sentient.
- Thus P→Q
- Indeed, you can even think about purely hypothetical individuals (let’s say they’re aliens), stipulate that they meet the disjunct and be comfortable in saying that they are persons.
- For instance, suppose you see an entity which shares absolutely no physical similarity to human beings. At this point, with the given information, it would be pretty difficult to make a moral evaluation about this thing (it could just be a rock). However, let’s stipulate that this being possesses non-trivial sentience (has a non-trivial interest N at t where t is the present). Basically, it has mental contents like you and I. With just this one fact, it seems that we are licensed to make claims about this individual's moral status. Thus, knowing that an entity is non-trivially sentient means that it is a person.
- Thus = Q→P
- Because P→Q and Q→P are equivalent to, P↔Q, we can say that P↔Q has been proven.
- Proof by Contraposition
- In logic, the contrapositive of a statement has its antecedent and consequent negated and swapped. The resulting formula is logically equivalent to the original. Given their equivalence, the reason this is useful is because contrapositives can be (trivially) used as proofs for conditionals.
- Suppose you have what seems to be a human person in front of you. They appear and act as though they are a normal human being. Yet, you find out that this being is merely a highly sophisticated robot with someone controlling it, which itself has never nor is having any sentient experiences.
- Notice here that every physical fact true of a human is true of the robot, yet, upon learning the one fact about this being’s lack of sentience, we are willing to say the entity is not a person.
- Thus ¬Q→¬P
- Think about anything which isn’t a person (chairs, tables, silverware) and upon reflection, none of these things are non-trivially sentient.
- Thus ¬P→¬Q
- Combined with my last argument, we have extremely strong reasons to favour the proposed theory. We know that when the proposed criteria is instantiated, an entity is a person, and when the proposed criteria isn’t instantiated, the entity is not a person.
- Accounting for auxiliary interests
- The second part of the disjunct (N is in E’s interest at t and B is capable of having an interest in N at t) is necessary for preserving the rights of individuals who may not presently cognise them. For instance, suppose that an individual is in a coma, and hence not processing any desires. Clearly, we want to say that this person still has rights. Hence, this theory states that given they have once had interests, it is rational to afford them a full set of human rights.
- Notice how this is not just an ad hoc maneuver. For a right to be, for example, violated, it must first exist ,which means that whatever gives one a right must exist prior to the time it is violated.
- Potential rebuke
- Pre sentient rights violations - I have argued for a biconditional between persons (and their moral entitlements) and sentience. A critic may attempt to point at specific entities which we deem to be persons, but does not have sentience. Suppose that we have a baby who has never been sentient, but will be in five minutes. Since such an entity has never been sentient, it is not protected under the proposed rights theory, and hence killing it is perfectly fine, yet, it is argued that such a killing seems to be highly immoral.
- I argue that this hypothetical is not problematic. Imagine one takes this pre sentient baby and replicates it (including the fact that it will be sentient in 5 minutes). However, they have replicated it in such a way that its biological constitution has been entirely replaced with synthetic materials and fabric. It is, in essence, a doll which is about to be sentient. In this case, is there a person being harmed when the doll is being destroyed? It seems that there is not. We can clearly understand that the doll is not a person, and will only become one after sentience. Given this, it's also recognisable that there is no obligation to bring what could be a person into existence (otherwise we would be obligated into impregnating people all day).
- If we understand that killing a pre sentient doll does not violate a being's moral entitlement, and all the moral predicates true of the doll are also true of the baby, it follows that killing a pre sentient baby also doesn’t involve any rights violations.
- Note how per p1, killing the doll can still be wrong even if the doll is not sentient. For instance, even though my neighbour's doll is not a person (or have moral entitlements), that does not mean I can snatch it out of their hand and rip its head off. Trivially, things can be wrong even if they do not involve rights violations.
- The medical consensus on when a fetus first gains sentience is 22 weeks, with some postulating it to be as late as 30 weeks.
- In addition, a fetal electroencephalogram shows alternation between signs of being asleep and being awake only at or after thirty weeks of gestation.
- Thus, it seems unlikely that the fetus is sentient until at least after twenty weeks of gestation. The fetus satisfies neither disjunct of the proposed theory and is hence not a person.
- Because 93% of abortions happen before 13 weeks gestation, almost every abortion falls clearly outside of the parameter within which the fetus gains sentience. Thus, abortion does not violate the rights of any moral entity.
- Because the argument takes the form of modus ponens and the premises are true, the argument is sound and the conclusion that abortion does not violate the moral entitlements of a person is upheld.
- We now know that the fetus is not a person (where most abortions are concerned) so abortion does not violate the fetus’ rights. But this fact alone doesn’t justify abortions permissibility. Indeed, just because a child’s doll doesn’t have rights does not mean that I can rip it up or steal it (this would violate someone else’s rights, namely the child) These would be morally unacceptable consequences.
- However, I argue that no such consequences exist in the case of abortion.
- The mother is the clearest stakeholder in abortions. Given abortions are only pursued because the mother has sought to undergo such treatment, it cannot be said that her rights are being violated.
- That this decision is free and informed is corroborated by the fact that most people who get abortions do not regret it.
- Countries where abortions are legal tend to have higher GDP than countries with restrictive legislation.
- Furthermore, countries with access to legal abortions is correlated with higher average economic freedom.
- It is widely recognised that the abolition of abortion has deleterious consequences. As Tyrer (1985) found, “if abortions were again made illegal, the number of illegal abortions in the US would probably increase from fewer than 20,000 at present to more than 1,000,000 per year. Because illegal abortion may carry a risk of death as much as 30 times that of legal abortion, deaths to women of reproductive age in the US would be expected to increase”.
- If abortion is banned, the mortality rates would increase by 7% within a year and 21% over subsequent years post-abortion ban.
- Psychological research indicates that abortions are not linked to mental health problems.
- Contrary to common pro-life belief, abortion is not linked to infertility or breast cancer.
- Thus abortion carries neither psychological or physical problems.
- Thus, abortion does not have any morally unacceptable non-rights violation outcomes.
- As abortion neither violates the fetus’ rights nor has unacceptable consequences, abortion is permissible.
- Savant’s criteria for personhood can be inferred as stating “an entity E is a person if and only if they can be harmed”, where harm is defined as “impeding bodily functions”. There are several reasons why this is uncompelling.
- Philosophical zombies
- A P zombie is an entity who is physically identical to human beings but lacks the ability to deploy sentience.
- Under Savants definition, P zombies are persons who can be harmed. They are organisms which go through mitosis and will grow unless impeded, have limbs which can be removed and stomachs that can be starved. Yet, this is clearly absurd. P zombies lack attributability, accountability and answerability and hence neither demand now fulfil moral obligations. To cut the arm off a p zombie is equivalent to cutting the arm off a doll.
- What’s the answer?
- It seems that mere impediment to biological bodies does not unequivocally imply harm. What’s missing is a subject of rights violations. My proposed theory of personhood accounts for this - p zombies aren’t persons because they’ve never been sentient.
- Savant claims that killing is wrong regardless of the stage of development of an entity, therefore, killing the fetus is wrong despite its early stage of development. This argument clearly targets only those who believe that killing can be justified by the stage of development of a person (probably no one intelligent). Under my proposed view, killing the fetus isn’t wrong because of the fetus’ age, rather, it is wrong because the fetus lacks sentience.
- Savant further provides the pre sentient rights violations counterexample. As this has already been addressed, I will only provide two recapitulating remarks. The example demands answers to the following two questions:
- 1. Does killing the baby violate its rights?
- 2. Does killing the baby plausibly entail morally unacceptable outcomes?
- The answer to 1 is clearly no, and the answer to 2 is ambiguous. Given the evidence that killing pre sentient beings in the womb doesn’t have deleterious effects on society (p3) there’s no reason to think that killing pre sentient beings which are a bit older will have any drastically different effect. In any case, this case fails to establish what Savant desires, which is that the baby’s rights are being violated by its killing.
- The FLO account of harm is overly permissive in what it deems to be immoral.
- Robot rights
- Suppose that an engineer assembles a highly complex robot which is capable of having human experiences. However they must charge the robot and let it reach 100% battery before it can deploy its first ever conscious experience. When the robot is 75% charged, the scientists begin having doubts as to the ramifications of their project, so they shut it down and abandon the robot. Is what the scientist did wrong?
- Under the FLO account of harm, it is. There is a being who is already “growing” (or charging), it doesn’t require adding any bodily functions, and it will become a person if it is not impeded. Yet, we would be reluctant to say that the robot has been harmed. Notice how my proposed theory does account for this. The robot has never been sentient, so killing it isn't wrong. Notice further how if we stipulate the robot has gone through the stage of sentience and has developed interests and desires, we would suddenly be weary as to permitting its killing. Whereas FLO ignores this nuance and categorises both these examples as equivalent, the pro-sentience position is furnished with the tools to adjudicate these scenarios.
- Nothing here is important to my argument. Given I deny you can harm non persons, the direct vs indirect harm distinction is meaningless. Furthermore, since I deny that the fetus is a person, I deny that it has any obligations let alone a special one.
- To recall, the argument being defended takes the following form
- The sub argument presented was as follows
- “Disembodied heads and corpses fit the conjunct”
- Two points can be raised here.
- First, the criticism is not true. Given the conjunct, explicated in full in p2.1, corpses are not capable of having interests given death is, by definition, the cessation of bodily functions and sentience. In particular, the qualification that B must have desires from t - n through t excludes dying during this time (because when you’re dead any desire you have is terminated).
- Note that this cannot be said of coma patients because they do retain their beliefs, desires, etc., as evidence by the fact that they have not forgotten them when they wake up.
- Second, even if the criticism were true, the resolution would not hold, for CON could easily explicate that the being will be sentient in the future (note that I’m not making this move, but just demonstrating that nothing is really at stake). In any case, the criticism does not threaten CON's position.
- “Killing a presentient baby is not abductively virtuous”
- Savant mistakes abduction with prima facie justification. Whilst one may “intuitively” think that killing such an entity is wrong, such an evaluation has nothing to do with abduction. E.g., we may intuitively think the Earth is flat, but our cumulative abductive reasons (given to us by science) to believe otherwise prevail.
- As I have extensively discussed in r1, there is nothing one can point to about killing a pre-sentient fetus which is actually wrong. All moral predicates true of the baby are true of a hypothetical pre-sentient plastic doll, which intuitively, we acknowledge is not a person. Given this, we have no basis for treating the entity differently.
- “Babies with artificial limbs are persons”
- Savant offers this verbally loaded biting of the bullet (I say it is loaded because "baby" usually refers to pre-sentient) that we should care about plastic dolls which have never been sentient and yet will in a couple minutes.
- This position is highly unintuitive. To really illustrate it, imagine you have some old barbie doll, and God comes down to tell you that in an hour's time, he will endow this doll with the sentience of a normal human baby. It seems clear that, in this hour, the doll is not a person yet nor has any moral entitlements. In the same way that we have no obligation to have sex to create a person, we have an obligation to protect this barbie to create a person.
- You can think about this reductio in reference to any arbitrary object. Take a grain of sand. If Savant were informed that a grain of sand would in an hour become a sentient human being if it is not crushed (let’s say God ensures this conditional), they would be committed to saying that crushing this grain of sand is as morally bad as killing a grown human being. In fact, under the FLO account, if the grain of sand were to transform into a sentient being with 80 years of valuable experiences, and the grown human in being is an 80 year old man, Savant would think that cracking this grain of sand is worse than killing such a man.
- Contrast this CON’s proposed theory where harm is indexed to sentient entities, where killing the man would be trivially far worse.
- “The reductio also applies to your position”
- Attempting to apply the reductio to the proposed theory fails, given all that is yielded is a fully sentient doll which we would trivially say is a person. We are comfortable saying that if a doll were sentient like you or I, it is a person with moral entitlements. What we are not comfortable with saying is that if a doll were just some normal plastic toy, it has rights if it could become something we care about in the future.
- “Why is it wrong to kill a comatose patient but not a brain dead person ”
- As explicated above, comatose patients are capable of sentience whereas brain dead people are by definition, not able to, hence the moral distinction. Note further that the proposed theory is a substance theoretic view on personhood. It is supposed to articulate who is a person and who is not, and not strictly for assessing who is more valuable and who is not. Certainly, a potential sentence is an important characteristic, but only when it is indexed to a person.
- A really important thing to note here is that I don’t have any objection to worrying about potential harm. The issue comes when Savant tries to index harm to someone who is not a person.
- “Mailing $100 dollars example”
- Clearly, this action would be wrong because it has “morally unacceptable consequences”, a consideration accounted for by p2 (non rights violative immoralities).
- I extend that abortion does not violate any stakeholders rights, and that women do not regret having abortions.
- I claimed that countries with legal abortion tend to have a higher GDP. Savant claims that CON has failed to establish that abortions cause an increase in GDP. This is not my claim. Per the subtitle, I am providing inductive reasons to think that abortion does not harm society at large. Given it is extraordinarily difficult to prove a negative claim of this kind, we have to be complacent with correlative works. The strongest evidence in favour of the is that Savant cannot provide evidence that abortion harms society at large, and this is evidenced by the fact that more often than not, first world, prosperous and free countries seem to have legal access.
- Savant claims that permitting abortions would be deleterious for society, since it kills 630, 000 unborn lives (hence the workforce is reduced, etc). This claim presupposes that the fetus is a person (which is not the subject of p3). Since these lives are not persons, this is completely irrelevant. This would be akin to saying that “the government not mandating adults have sex twice a week means that X number of potential babies are not being born, which correlates to $X loss in GDP and X number of potential workers”.
- I claimed that society would face huge demonstrable risks if abortion is banned. Savant refutes this by claiming that this debate is not about legality. However, this misinterprets the specific argument CON is proposing. The claim being made is that if we assess abortion to be immoral and see it (as Savant proposes) as akin to murder, the entailment of this position is abolition, which itself must be considered when assessing whether abortion has morally unacceptable consequences (per p3).
- Savant also claims that the harm of illegal abortions count in favour of the proposition that abortions are immoral. This claim is akin to saying that being black in the 60’s is bad, because you have a higher chance of getting lynched. Obviously, the wrong maker in both cases lies outside of the intrinsic moral calculation of the individual/action. An abortion wouldn't harmful if not for restrictive laws, and being black wouldn't be bad if it weren't for lynchers.
- Recall that this section pertains to “morally unacceptable consequences”, not whether the fetus is a person. Given there are no deleterious social consequences that have been demonstrated, the premise holds.
- Savant claims that P zombies are not harmed because they will not develop consciousness. Note that consciousness is not mentioned in Savants “Criteria for Personhood”, “Definition of Harm” or “Support for this Definition”. Given this, it cannot be reasonably inferred that developing consciousness is the key determining factor for harm.
- Under this revised interpretation (where a person is that who will develop consciousness), this just seems to be another FLO argument, which has been addressed in the FLO section.
- “Alleged dropped argument”
- A lot (almost every one) of the things Savant alleges CON to have dropped can be responded to in the same way. In this particular case, killing a child is plausibly worse than killing an adult. But the proposed view on personhood is only supposed to get you so far as to say that they are both persons (it is after all just a personhood criterion). There’s no issue with saying that killing the child is worse because they could have potential sentience, because the child is already a person and hence can be subjects of harm
- “Revised Coma Analogy”
- (I recommend reading Savant's analogy before reading my response as I will not pasting it in its entirety here)
- “Presumably we would say that they deprived the child of a long life and that many opportunities were stolen from them”
- In particular, we would say that a person has been deprived of a long life. Indeed, claiming a child has been harmed only makes sense if the child is a person. Thus, CON’s framework still undergirds any claim that such a murderer is wrong.
- “Suppose the murderer revealed that the comatose child was actually not sentient in the past… Con’s view holds that this information alone should absolve the killer of any moral culpability”.
- Per the argument presented in I. Permissibility of abortion actions are wrong if they violate moral entitlements or have morally unacceptable consequences. Just because in this case the child is revealed to not have moral entitlements does not mean the action is morally acceptable.
- For example, suppose there is a sting operation where a man hires a hitman (who is actually a government agent) to kill his wife. Because it is a set up, no one is ever close to being assassinated. Even though there is no rights violation in this situation, the action still has morally unacceptable consequences.
- In the same way, telling the parents of comatose children that their child has been murdered is not a rights violation (because the child isn’t a person by definition), but that does not in any way make it any more permissible. The action is wrong in the same way that hiring a sting hitman is wrong (which is to say, very wrong).
- “Alleged dropped argument”
- Same as above. Missed opportunities are harmful insofar as they are indexed to a person.
- Engineer example
- I recommend voters reread my engineer counterexamples to the FLO before reading Savant's rebuttal and my reply.
- “The robot isn’t growing or doing anything with the energy yet to push itself toward a form capable of having conscious experiences. However, an unborn child has an internal growth process that pushes it toward sentience even though said process must be aided by external nutrients”
- This is a difference without substance. Given this is an analogy, CON can just stipulate into the hypothetical that all these facts are true. Just as how the unborns internal growth is “pushing” itself towards an eventual sentient experience through the aid of external nutrients (the mother umbilical cord) it can be stipulated that the robot is also “pushing” and “developing” itself and using external nutrients (the charger) to fulfil this end.
- “Unplugging the charger doesn’t disrupt any internal processes in the robot”
- This is completely wrong. It can be stipulated in the hypothetical that the robot is using the energy to sustain its internal processes of eventually gaining sentience, and that absent the charging, the robot will not have the “nutrients” to sustain itself, and will eventually become unserviceable.
- Ultimately, Savant tries to circumvent the analogy with odd naturalistic fallacies (like saying that charging isn’t a bodily function, the robot isn’t growing etc). This makes no sense given FLO doesn’t place any restrictions on substrate, and cares about pure potentiality (so the vehicle of the FLO should never matter).
- To challenge Savant on this point, I ask them specifically - what needs to be true of the robot such that killing it becomes immoral? CON has already stipulated that the robot has internal processes (some wires and electricity), is developing (using the energy from the charger to grow) and that it will experience sentience in the near future (like a fetus). Simply, there is no trait left that can be equalised, besides some unconvincing appeal to the moral primacy of biological flesh (which frankly is the only distinction left).
- Voters can recognise that the engineer's robot is, in all philosophically relevant respects, identical to a pre-sentient baby. Because it is clearly absurd to say that such a robot is a person, the FLO account of rights fails.
- “ Hence, voters should accept this premise as given; if a fetus has personhood, the resolution is affirmed”
- This is clearly incorrect, per p1 of the original argument. Things can be wrong even if there is no person who is being violated (recall the hitman example).
- A keen eye may observe that this seems to exclude hypothetical babies who have never been sentient, but will be in a short period of time. Surely it’s wrong to kill these individuals?
- To address this, I (in the first round mind you) presented a symmetrical case in an attempt to show why the analogy is not so absurd. Take this baby which we intuitively think has moral entitlements, by virtue of it almost being sentient (note that it is this trait which the objector maintains is problematic) . Now, let’s say that we replicate this baby, where its skin becomes plastic, its organs become synthetic and its hair becomes thread. It is, in ordinary parlance, a doll, except that it will in the future become sentient (remember this is the trait which is being tested). In this case, would it be wrong to kill such a doll? The answer seems to be no. Why would we care about some plastic doll just because in the future it could become something we care about (note how sperm and egg also could become something we care about, yet most of us don’t consider masturbation a sin.)?
- Savant provides several responses to this defence
- “It’s not abductively virtuous”
- This point was already refuted. Abduction is an inference to the best explanation not the first explanation. Just because something is not immediately intuitive does not count against it as an explanation, just like how the world intuitively seeming to be prima facie flat does not provide abductive justification for this position. Savant attempts to refute this reply by saying that I don’t defend my position with science like the globe earther does but this is obviously a tangential point. This does not challenge the initial rebuttal that immediate intuitions furnish abductive justifications.
- “It’s needlessly complicated”
- First, the example is clearly not complicated - the reason for selecting a doll is to remove the fact that it is a human being in question (an inherently normatively loaded category) with something neutral, to assess whether the trait being questioned is actually problematic.
- Second, complication is no defence. Consider Davidson’s ostensibly ridiculous “swamp man” analogy as a prominent example.
- “Attempted reversal”
- Savant specifically claims “Con also holds that (a) a person who has temporarily transformed into a non sentient doll, and (b) a doll that was sentient in the past and will be in the future, are persons”.
- Both of these points are essentially equivalent to the “corpses fit the conjunct” criticism which Savant has dropped (the response can be read here and stands uncontested). In short
- A standard non sentient doll (without the predicate of “will be sentient”) is not capable of sentience and hence a transformation into it is equivalent to death.
- Even if this were an issue, CON can just stipulate that a person has to be sentient in the future. In any case, the rebuttal has no impact on the resolution.
- “Biting the bullet”
- Savant seems to bite the bullet when stating that given the ability to apply my theory to such an entity, they would say that the entity is a person, but it makes no sense to apply our intuition to dolls since this being is hardly an ordinary doll.
- Savant has gotten it completely backwards. The question being asked is “does it make sense to kill an entity E who is at the stage of pre-sentience”. Savant argues it doesn’t and substitutes E with a pre-sentient baby. I argue it does and substitute E with a doll. Clearly then, the ickiness of pre sentient babies elicited when selecting an E which is normatively loaded (a baby, thereby begging the question), and the ickiness disappears when selecting something normatively neutral (a doll). Given this, we can see the power of Savant's critique exists only when we consider an entity who we already usually think is a person, and not when we consider a normatively neutral entity.
- This analogy was presented here by Savant. Essentially, given my criteria of past and present sentience, Savant argues that someone could hypothetically kill a mothers child and exonerate themself if they reveal that the baby was never actually sentient. I claimed that this is a clear violation of p3 given its unacceptable social consequences.
- Savant's latest rebuttal claims that under my theory, the wrongness of such an action is indexed to the mother, and that absent her negative feelings, the action would be considered heroic. This is clearly incorrect. Suppose a man hires a hitman to kill his wife. Yet, the hitman is actually a government agent, and the wife is in on it. So the man pays the hitman to have his wife “killed”, without knowing that no such action will ever take place. Now suppose that the wife gets cold feet and in a heap of irrationality, pleads for her husband to be free. She is so convincing that even the government agents start sympathising for her. In such a case, it is clear that despite the feelings of the victim or even those around, actions can still be immoral. In Savant's analogy, the wrongness of killing the baby is not indexed to the mothers psychological states.
- The FLO account of harm can be thoroughly dismantled with the engineer example (first presented here). Despite this being my primary criticism of their entire position, Savant unfortunately does not offer much defence in the last round, opting to group this with the doll analogy.
- However, the final remark on the analogy seems to be a bite of the bullet - “with this stipulation, I would hold that a non sentient “robot” in the process of gaining sentience is no less a person than a currently-sentient robot or a robot that used to be sentient and will regain sentience”.
- Voters should recognise how absurd this is. To say that not charging a robot to 100% battery and preventing it from deploying sentience is tantamount to murder is simply ridiculous. The FLO account makes no distinction between preventing this robot from being charged with killing a standard human person. Hence, Savants accounts of rights should be vehemtly rejected.
- Contrast this to CON’s proposed theory, which does respect this critical distinction. Because the doll has never been sentient, there is obviously nothing wrong with not charging it and giving it a sentient experience, and doing so is certainly incomparable to murder.
- To show how absurd Savant's position is, I raised the sand analogy (first presented here). Essentially, because the FLO account only places the FLO as its only predicate for affording personhood (and not any restrictions on what this being may be), a grain of sand can be said to have rights. If we say that an omnipotent deity makes it such that a given grain of sand will in an hour mutate into a sentient being, it will satisfy the criteria of having an FLO and under Savant's view, be a person.
- Savant tries to refute this by saying that the sand requires something to add its bodily function. This can easily be stipulated away in the proposed analogy. It can be said that the omnipotent deity has made it such that every molecule in the grain of sand, upon divine intervention, is slowly acting in such a way that it will become a sentient entity at some future time.
- Voters might think this is absurd, but such an example is simply a consequence of Savants position. Under their theory of harm, all that matters is whether an entity can be deprived of a future. A counter example can be constructed if we just imagine that some arbitrary object (like a grain of sand) is developing in such a way that in some future time, it will become sentient. Under Savant's view, breaking this object is tantamount to murder.
- The issue could be better illuminated when considering CON’s remedy. Given my proposed theory does place restrictions on features which the entity must currently possess (it must currently be sentient or have been sentient), rocks and sand are immediately excluded.
- This has been dropped throughout the debate and should be taken as conceeded.
- In defence of this premise, I presented studies which suggeted that abortion access is correlated with economic freedom. Savant rightly points out the correlation is not causation. However, the burden of proof to substantiate the positive claim is on Savant. Imagine you wanted to prove that legal drug access didn’t harm society. One way could be to show that countries with legal access are generally happier. Even though this is correlative, it still provides prima facie reason for believing in the proposition. However, the strongest evidence for the statement is the absence of any positive justification for the contrary - that is, proof that drug uses causes social disharmony. So whilst causation may be preferenced over correlation, the burden is ultimately on Savant to prove that abortion has negative effects on society.
- I argued that preventing abortions from occuring would harm society. I showed this by pointing at the dangers of illegal abortions. Savant attempted to refute this by saying that the harms of illegal abortions count in favour for the proposition (they actually said this here). I rejoined by pointing out the clear absurdity of this - just like how the badness of being black in the 60’s comes from a racist society, the badness of illegal abortions comes from harmful legislation.
- Savants latest rebuttal is to say that being black is not a choice whereas getting an abortion is. This is a completely tangential rebuttal which fails to capture my response. Instead of being black in the 60’s the example can be substituted with acting out homosexuality (I specify “acting out” so Savant cannot say that it is not a choice). Clearly then, the baddness of being gay in the 60’s come from society, yet it would be absurd to make the argument that “being gay is bad because you’ll get attacked”, when the wrong maker clearly lies in the hands of society.
- I argued that legal abortions are safe, and beneficial to women's mental health. This was never disputed by Savant, hence it stands conceded.
- Savant fails to understand the purpose of this premise . In assessing the social impacts, we are not considering whether the action is a moral violation (that dispute was left in p2). This premise asks whether there are undesirable social consequences. For instance, suppose we apply my syllogism to test whether drug legalisation is moral, and per p2, we find that (strangely) every instance of drug use is so dehabiliting that its users cannot provide informed consent and hence have their rights violated. Having established this, if we then move on the p3 to consider whether there are any deleterious social impacts (does drug use affect communities, GDP, family, etc), we would not go back to pointing at the rights violation that drug use entails. Thus, Savant commits the same category error.
- (Basically all of Savants arguments here commit the same error so keep this point in mind)
- This argument fails for the above reasons. In calculating loss of GDP, the paper begs the question by considering the unborn to be people who are tangible economic stakeholders. Its success hinges on the presupposition that the unborn are people, which is precisely what is not what is up for debate in this section (that would be for p2). As such, this rebuttal simply begs the question in favour of the resolution.
My vote: Pro
Pro: Consistently maintained a clear line of moral reasoning.
Con: Good direct rebuttals but less precise about why uncertainty is not sufficient.
Reasons:
Pro's “uncertainty principle” was never fully dismantled. Con challenged it but didn’t show it was unreasonable.
The autonomy defense was strong from con but relied on 'asserting' that bodily autonomy beats potential personhood without fully showing why that moral perspective outweighs the
precautionary harm.
Pro suggested and maintained a layered ethical framework (FLO, special obligations, uncertainty) throughout the debate.
Whereas con primarily offered counter-assertions and did not develop a comparable alternative moral framework.
I think Pro’s arguments were more compelling on balance. Pro demonstrated that even under uncertainty about personhood, the moral risk of abortion equates to potentially committing severe harm (comparable to homicide).
Con did effectively argue for autonomy, but he did not sufficiently counter the moral weight of the 'precautionary principle' or establish why bodily autonomy rejects that moral uncertainty.
Plus, con’s engagement with the 'Future-Like-Ours' argument was more dismissive than refutative.
Thus in my opinion, pro stood to their burden more convincingly.
Further reason for decision of best legibility: pro’s writing was clearer, better structured, and easier to follow.
Plus: Arguments were numbered and labeled (“1. Uncertainty,” “2. FLO,” etc.). I don't know how much this counts.
Yeah that’s right. You should definitely look into voting.
Don't use open voting for something like this, you will always get the idiots
Rage bait votes use to be believable
Looking forward to it!
All wrapped up - I think you'll enjoy this one a lot.
Probably don’t need me to say this, but when this is done, definitely hit me up for a vote. I know you both are excellent on this topic.
I realise that in the conclusion and else where, I used "pre sentient" to describe my criteria (to describe previously sentient). This is obviously confusing given I use "pre sentient" to also describe beings who have never been sentient. Hopefully this isn't too boggling but I'm sure you'll be able to tell which usage refers to what.
Oops
Wait, isnt Bones Pro for this topic?
One week is fine
Actually, would one week argument time be possible? If not that should be alright but I would prefer it.
Should I leave it up until then or take it down and repost in a week or so?
My schedule is a bit up in the air right now but I should be able to accept this at latest within two weeks. The definitions and burden are both good.
Lmk if these specifications work for you