Instigator / Pro
1485
rating
92
debates
45.65%
won
Topic
#6330

Resolved: God is the best explanation for morality

Status
Debating

Waiting for the next argument from the contender.

Round will be automatically forfeited in:

00
DD
:
00
HH
:
00
MM
:
00
SS
Parameters
Publication date
Last updated date
Type
Standard
Number of rounds
4
Time for argument
One week
Max argument characters
10,000
Voting period
Two weeks
Point system
Winner selection
Voting system
Open
Contender / Con
1485
rating
3
debates
33.33%
won
Description

Thank you, Double_R, for accepting this debate!

Note this debate will be winner select

INTRO

In this debate I will be arguing for one major contention: God is the best explanation of morality. By that, I mean that the existence of objective moral facts is best explained by positing the existence of a supreme being. By "best explanation." I mean it is superior to competing theories in terms of its explanatory scope, explanatory power, plausibility, less ad hocness, accord with already accepted beliefs, and comparative superiority. The argument goes like this [1}:

1. If God does not exist, objective moral values do not exist.
2. Objective moral values do exist.
3. Therefore, God exist
.
=== Definitions ==
Morality: principles concerning the distinction between right and wrong or good and bad behavior.
Moral realism:
Objective: True regardless of human opinions.

-- STRUCTURE --
1. Opening
2. Rebuttals
3. Rebuttals
4. Rebuttals/Close

Rules
1. No forfeits
2. Citations must be provided in the text of the debate
3. No new arguments in the final speeches
4. Observe good sportsmanship and maintain a civil and decorous atmosphere
5. No trolling
6. No "kritiks" of the topic (challenging assumptions in the resolution)
7. For all resolutional terms, individuals should use commonplace understandings that fit within the logical context of the resolution and this debate
8. The BOP is on Pro; Con's BOP lies in proving Pro wrong. Con may make original arguments if he wants to.
9. Rebuttals of new points raised in an adversary's immediately preceding speech may be permissible at the judges' discretion even in the final round (debaters may debate their appropriateness)
11. Violation of any of these rules merits a loss.

== SOURCES ==
1. https://www.reasonablefaith.org/podcasts/defenders-podcast-series-1/s1-moral-argument/moral-argument-part-1

Round 1
Pro
#1
Intro

I want to say thank you to Double_R for accepting this debate. In this debate I will need to defend two things: (1) Moral realism - that morality is objective; and (2) That moral realism necessitates a God. The basic structure goes like this [1]:

1. If God does not exist, objective moral values do not exist.
2. Objective moral values do exist.
3. Therefore, God exist

Premise 2: Objective moral values exist

I’m actually going to begin my arguments by defending premise 2 before I defend premise 1. Premise 2 is where the bulk of this debate will probably be focused on. Why should we believe that moral facts are objective? Here are a few reasons:

(1) Moral progress 

Moral progress only makes sense in the framework of moral realism. Almost everyone can agree that slavery is wrong and that the abolition of slavery was an improvement on society. But why should we believe this is the case? If morality were merely subjective or based on culture, then who is to say that we actually made progress as a society? 

Consider the following statistics: In Yemen, under the oppressive forces of the Youthis, gay people are routinely imprisoned and sentenced to death [2], enslaves children [3], and restrict women’s freedom of movement [4].  Most people would rightly be repulsed by such behavior. But why should we be repulsed? If morality was merely subjective or based on culture, then who are we to say Yemen’s culture is worse than ours?

(2) The objective nature of morality allows for moral judgement 

Consider the above examples from Yemen. We are certainly repulsed at the notions of child slavery. But why? If morality is nothing more than one's mere opinion, then it makes no sense condemning or praising someone. Under moral anti-realism or subjectivism, stating “slavery is immoral” is like saying “wearing white after labor day is wrong.”  But we intuitively know that there are things that are objectively right and wrong, like child slavery. 

(3) Argument from Epistemic Realism

Consider the following dialogue:

David: What do you think of my argument for evolution?
Double_R: I think it's a sound argument -- your conclusion was well-argued, and I see no problems with it.
David: So does that mean you'll reject young earth creationism now and accept the scientific facts of evolution?
Double_R: No
David: Why not?
Double_R: Because I have no duty to embrace the truth. I reject reality and substitute it with my own. 

Such an exchange is rightfully absurd. If there are epistemic facts and duties, then why are there no moral facts and duties? In the context of this debate I am sure my opponent would have me be respectful of him, honestly engage with his arguments, and not commit logical fallacies. But why is that the case? We can summarize this as follows [5]:

P1. If moral facts do not exist, then epistemic facts do not exist.
P2: Epistemic facts do exist
C1: Moral facts do exist. 
P3: If moral facts do exist, then moral realism is true. 
C2: Moral realism is true

Consider the following principles and values which are foundational to the very possibility of rational discourse, all of which the moral anti-realists must deny:

1. It is good to believe the truth and avoid falsehood.
2. We ought to think rationally.
3. We ought to argue from an honest perspective.
4. We ought not misrepresent your opponent's arguments.
5. You must not commit logical fallacies. 

If relativism or nihilism about value entails such conclusions, then it can be rightly rejected as absurd. Given the ubiquity and centrality of rational discourse in everyday life, we have every reason to suppose that there are such things as objective moral facts.

Premise 1: If God does not exist, objective moral values do not exist 

Now that we have established moral realism, why should we accept the first premise? If moral realism is true, that means there is an objective  source that can account for morality. This means that the source of morality must be transcend humanity, be morally perfect, be a rational entity, and be necessary. This being is what we call God. 

Objection: Euthyphro’s dilemma

There is a famous argument made by Euthyphro that attempts to undermine the divine origins of ethics. The argument states: “do the gods love good action because it is good, or is good action good because it is loved by the gods?” 

The problem is that this is a false dilemma. Morality is not good because God says it is good nor is it good because it is already good independent of God, but rather morality reflects the moral perfection of God’s nature.

Conclusion

Objective moral values and duties exist, as shown by progress, judgment, and epistemic realism. These require a personal, morally perfect God to ground ethics. The resolution is strongly affirmed. 

Sources
5. Michael Jones, "Moral Realism Defended." https://youtu.be/zjkgD4w9w1k?si=fgWg7NfYThtSr3PL&t=42 


Con
#2
Thanks to David for this debate, looking forward to a good discussion.

I want to begin by addressing Pro's syllogism offered in the prior round with the aim of avoiding any confusion. While I think his arguments stay on track with regards to the scope of this debate, his stated conclusion from premises one and two "therefore God exists" veers off track. The resolution in this debate is that God "best explains" morality, so that is what I will focus on. Even though God must exist in order to affirm the resolution, proving his existence is a conversation for another day, so that is not what I will be addressing here.

With that, I will not challenge the logical structure of Pro's argument. Instead, I will focus my case on two points: that objective moral values do not exist, and that even if they somehow do, God is not only not the best explanation but is, in fact, an insufficient one.

Objective Moral Values Do Not Exist

Part 1: Clarifying Definitions

To understand why this is the case, we need to begin with an in depth understanding of what these terms mean in the first place.

The first word I’ll single out here is “values.” I’ve always found it odd that proponents of this argument use a term that is, by definition, subjective. But I think a minor tweak is all that’s necessary to correct this, so I will disregard it for now and focus on the more central terms at play here.

Exist: This is another term I find semantically problematic. To exist is to “have being” according to most dictionaries. I don’t think that’s what Pro is arguing, although he can make that case if he wishes. When it is said that objective morality exists, what’s really being said is that moral judgments are objective in the same way that 2+2=4 is objective. That is, you cannot point to any of these in reality, only to representations of them as ideas.

So with that, I offer a more clarifying way to phrase this contention: “moral judgments are objectively determinable.”

The first of the two major terms here is “moral,” which is a product of morality. Morality is merely an assessment we make with regard to actions and intentions. If someone steals, we assess that as immoral absent any further context. The question is: why? Regardless of your position on God, the answer is the same: because it violates our moral standard. In other words, we begin with a standard for what morality constitutes, and then assess whether actions or intentions match up to that standard. If they do, we call that moral. If they do not, we call that immoral.

Objective is the final word to address here. What does it mean to be objective? I would offer the following: objectivity requires an assessment measured against that which either itself exists or can be manifested in reality.

For example, 2+2=4 is objective because we can empirically invoke its manifestation. One way to do so would be to put two cups on one side of the table and two cups on the other, then put them together and count how many cups we have. There is no argument or opinion involved. Reality will determine how many cups it adds up to; all we can do is observe and note.

A perhaps more analogous example is “the earth is round.” This example might seem a bit more nuanced to determine because we’d have to define “round” (since all those geometry geeks love to remind us the Earth is an oblate spheroid). But once the definition is settled, the assessment is again determined by reality itself, we simply match the Earth (which is empirical) to the definition.

Part 2: Why Moral Judgments Are Not Objectively Determinable

I will actually grant that they are, with one massive caveat - They are objectively determinable if we are beginning with an agreed upon moral standard. If we are not, then the question of whether an act is moral depends entirely on what we’re using for our standard of morality. That will always be subjective.

Pro will likely disagree. He will likely claim God is the only standard applicable. But that would be nothing more than an opinion, there is no grounding in reality necessitating that position. I can turn to Allah, or Zeus, or any other conception of a god, or I can turn to my own intuitions to create a moral standard. Pro will have no case as to how this does not qualify as a moral system under any reasonable definition of the term.

And herein lies the problem. If Pro is merely defining morality as that which is in accordance with God’s will, then he’s putting the cart before the horse. The resolution of this debate - that God “best explains” morality, already grants that the burden is on him to show God is the answer here, not merely define his position into victory.

My personal position on morality is that, while it is unquestionably subjective, if we are to function in this society with other people, we have to begin with a set of common values we generally share - such as a desire to live, a desire to remain healthy, a desire to enjoy personal freedom, and to have something to strive for. These basic values do not require a God for explanation, and yet from them we can easily see how things like empathy, compassion (resulting in a desire for the reduction of harm), and a desire for fairness are essential. With those as our foundation, our common understanding of basic moral “facts” is easily explainable.

I will leave it to Pro to decide whether he’d like me to explain and/or justify my moral system further. Till then, I’ll move on to my second contention.

God Is Insufficient as an Explanation

Pro cites the Euthyphro dilemma and claims to have solved it by stating that morality merely “reflects the moral perfection of God’s nature.” But this answer is just gibberish. God either has the power to rewrite the rules of morality or he does not. If he does not, then he cannot possibly be their author, and by extension, cannot possibly be their explanation. If he can, then morality would, by definition, be subject to his will (i.e., subjective). Either way, Pro’s position falls apart. His answer here is nothing more than an attempt to straddle the middle of a true dichotomy.

Moreover, even if God is the source of morality, that doesn’t change the fact that each individual would still have to decide for themselves whether to align their moral values with him. Anyone who does what God says only to appease him is not acting morally, that’s just self-preservation. To act morally requires pure intentions, not ulterior motives. Those motives can only come from within; thus, we are each individually still our own arbiter of what is moral. That makes our judgments, by definition, subjective.

Direct Rebuttals

Pro asks: “Who are we to say Yemen’s culture is worse than ours?”
Answer: we’re rationally thinking people who value well-being and fairness. Does that make us right? According to us, yes. Pro asks: how does it make sense to praise or condemn anyone if morality is “mere opinion”?

The answer is: because making sense is an assessment of logical validity, which is separate from the truth of the premises. Again, if we begin with values of well-being and fairness (my foundation), then the question answers itself. If we begin with God’s word as our foundation, then perhaps Pro can make sense of it. Either way, our foundation is still subject to each of us, individually.

Pro’s argument on epistemic facts does not work. What he’s calling attention to is ultimately nothing more than a subjective value. The truth is whatever it is, regardless of what we believe or want to be true. That doesn’t mean we have to care about it. In fact, many people don’t. Many people would much rather believe a comfortable lie over an uncomfortable truth. There’s an entire cultural meme dedicated to this concept (red pill vs. blue pill).

Summary

Pro’s case hinges on the idea that objective moral values exist, but they don’t, because the standard each of us uses as our moral foundation will always be up to each of us, i.e., subjective.

Moreover, Pro has failed not only to show how God can be invoked as the best explanation, but that he is a valid explanation at all.

The resolution stands negated.
Round 2
Pro
#3
Thank you, Double_R, for your response.

Re: Part 1: Clarifying Definitions

Category error 1: Conflating Moral Values with Subjective Preferences

My opponent begins by casting doubt on the existence of objective moral facts. My opponent states that  begins with a category mistake: Conflating personal values and moral values. My opponent states that values are by definition subjective but ignores what we mean by moral values. Russs Shafer-Landau writes “Moral values are objective if their truth does not depend on the attitudes or beliefs of any individual or group” [1]. For example, the wrongness of unnecessary harm, such as torturing infants for fun, and the value of honesty hold independently of opinion and social groups. My opponent's claim that values are subjective ignores this distinction, reducing moral facts to mere tastes, like preferring coca-cola over pepsi. 

Category error 2: Misunderstanding “Existence” in a Philosophical Context

The second category mistake my opponent makes is in his attempt to define existence. In metaphysics when we say something exists we say that it is mind-independent, i.e., that its reality does not depend on an observer. For example, my computer exists whether or not anyone is looking at it or not [2]. In the case of moral realism we are asserting that moral facts and duties are a part of reality and that they exist independently of any human mind and not as a matter of preference. 

Category error 3: Equivocating Epistemic Objectivity with Moral Ontology

So with that, I offer a more clarifying way to phrase this contention: “moral judgments are objectively determinable.”
Not only does this misrepresent my position but this is a third category mistake. My opponent mistakes epistemic objectivity with moral ontology. By attempting to reframe this as determinable my opponent shifts the debate on how we arrive at moral conclusions rather than the existence of moral facts. This debate is over whether or not moral facts exist not how we arrive at this conclusion. 

Category error 4: Ontological Objectivity with Empirical Verifiability

My opponent makes a 4th category mistake in his attempt to define objective. My opponent defines objective as:


What does it mean to be objective? I would offer the following: objectivity requires an assessment measured against that which either itself exists or can be manifested in reality.

By attempting to reduce objectivity into what we can observe or manifest again mistakes what philosophers mean by objective. By objective we mean something that is mind-independent: A statement that is true whether or not anyone believes or perceives them. This mistakes what is ontological objectivity (whether moral facts exist independently) and  epistemological verification (how we can confirm this).  Moreover my opponent begs the question: Why must objectivity be tied to empirical reality?

Re: Part 2: Why Moral Judgments Are Not Objectively Determinable

Category error 5: Epistemology  vs Ontology

I will actually grant that they are, with one massive caveat - They are objectively determinable if we are beginning with an agreed upon moral standard. If we are not, then the question of whether an act is moral depends entirely on what we’re using for our standard of morality. That will always be subjective.
Here my opponent again confuses epistemology with ontology. Just because there is a lack of consensus does not mean moral facts do not exist. For example, disagreements on scientific debates does not mean that the science is wrong or that the physical reality does not exist. This debate is not about whether or not we all agree on morality but whether or not these moral facts are mind-independent. Moreover, there is a very big inconsistency in my opponent's reply: My opponent also begs the questions: (1) Why does there need to be an agreed upon standard; and (2) If that agreed upon standard existed, why ought we follow those standards? 

Category error 6: Equating Moral Systems with Moral Facts

Pro will likely disagree. He will likely claim God is the only standard applicable. But that would be nothing more than an opinion, there is no grounding in reality necessitating that position. I can turn to Allah, or Zeus, or any other conception of a god, or I can turn to my own intuitions to create a moral standard. Pro will have no case as to how this does not qualify as a moral system under any reasonable definition of the term.
My opponent against conflates systems with facts. Just because there are differing systems (such as which God you choose) and the moral foundation. Just because one can construct a moral framework based on whichever God you choose does not mean that all systems are equally valid and it does not mean that none of them are grounded in objective truth.  In addition, my opponent makes the same mistake as he did earlier in this debate: Just because there are disagreements does not mean that objective moral facts do not exist or that God is not the foundation of morality.  Finally, my opponent misrepresents my position by framing it as definition rather than an ontological explanation. 

Category error 7: Conflating Moral Ontology with Defining Morality

And herein lies the problem. If Pro is merely defining morality as that which is in accordance with God’s will, then he’s putting the cart before the horse. The resolution of this debate - that God “best explains” morality, already grants that the burden is on him to show God is the answer here, not merely define his position into victory.

My personal position on morality is that, while it is unquestionably subjective, if we are to function in this society with other people, we have to begin with a set of common values we generally share - such as a desire to live, a desire to remain healthy, a desire to enjoy personal freedom, and to have something to strive for. These basic values do not require a God for explanation, and yet from them we can easily see how things like empathy, compassion (resulting in a desire for the reduction of harm), and a desire for fairness are essential. With those as our foundation, our common understanding of basic moral “facts” is easily explainable.

This is another category mistake. My opponent confuses ontology and defining morality and avoids the central claim that God's nature is what grounds objective truths. 


I will leave it to Pro to decide whether he’d like me to explain and/or justify my moral system further. Till then, I’ll move on to my second contention.

Please do! 

Re: God Is Insufficient as an Explanation

Category error 7: Conflating Moral Ontology with Divine Volition

Pro cites the Euthyphro dilemma and claims to have solved it by stating that morality merely “reflects the moral perfection of God’s nature.” But this answer is just gibberish. God either has the power to rewrite the rules of morality or he does not. If he does not, then he cannot possibly be their author, and by extension, cannot possibly be their explanation. If he can, then morality would, by definition, be subject to his will (i.e., subjective). Either way, Pro’s position falls apart. His answer here is nothing more than an attempt to straddle the middle of a true dichotomy.
This is my opponent's next category mistake and my opponent badly misunderstands the Theist position. God does not write the rules of morality, they are based on his perfect, immutable, and necessary nature. For example, under a theistic model murder is wrong not because it harms someone but because (1) each human being is created in God's image and (2) God nature is life. 

Moreover, even if God is the source of morality, that doesn’t change the fact that each individual would still have to decide for themselves whether to align their moral values with him. Anyone who does what God says only to appease him is not acting morally, that’s just self-preservation.
There are two category mistakes here: (1) confusing moral autonomy with ontology. Humans have free will. It is up to us to choose good or evil. Just because individuals choose to act a certain way does not make the truth of itself subjective; and (2) confusing moral rightness with motivation. An action can still be good or evil regardless of the motivation or if it is done for selfish reasons. 

“To act morally requires pure intentions...those motives can only come from within.”

But why ought our intentions be pure and why do they require pure intentions?  This just begs the question! If con wants to dictate that everyone must have pure intentions then he is unwittingly stating that there is at least one objective moral fact or value: We ought to act with pure intentions. 

Direct Rebuttals

I'll continue my rebuttals in the next round as I'm out of space to fully respond to this. My opponent begins with the values of well-being and fairness but why ought we act fairly? 

Conclusion

My opponent commits many many category errors and misrepresents key philosophical concepts. The resolution stands affirmed. 

Sources
1. Shafer-Landau, R. Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford University Press, 2003


Con
#4
My opponent's argument this past round focused primarily on two points; that I am confusing all of the main concepts involved in this debate, and repeated assertions of his central position. What he hasn't done is explained what reason we have to accept the asserted existence of said moral facts or tied that into how morality is best explained by God.

Response to Pro's critiques

Conflating Moral Values with Subjective Preferences

Pro claims I am conflating moral values with subjective preferences. But this isn't a conflation, that's my position in this debate. Pro is making the opposite claim here, he needs to rationally support his position, not merely assert it.

Misunderstanding “Existence” in a Philosophical Context

Pro claims I am making a mistake with regards to defining existence but never attempted to explain what that mistake was. His definition is perfectly compatible with what I offered, although I would argue far less useful. I'll expand on that shortly.

Equivocating Epistemic Objectivity with Moral Ontology

Pro claims I am equivocating these two, but it isn't an equivocation, it's a clarification. One cannot point to that which is (ontology) without delving into how we know what is (epistemology). To do so is to merely assert what is, defeating the purpose of a debate and abandoning his responsibility to provide rational support for his position.

Without an understanding of how we arrive at moral conclusions Pro leaves no basis for which to accept their existence at all. And even if we granted their existence for the sake of argument, the inability to reach their conclusions renders them useless with regards to explaining morality.

Ontological Objectivity with Empirical Verifiability

Pro claims I am attempting to "reduce" objectivity to that which manifests within realty. This isn't a reduction, it's how objectivity is understood in any meaningful context.

In every other discipline where objectivity is invoked such as science, logic or math, objectivity is derived from some form of empirical verification. To shield moral objectivity from this requirement is to give it special treatment. If there is no observable consequence grounding moral claims then their objectivity becomes unfalsifiable, making it practically and epistemologically useless.

Pro moves on to offer his definition which centers around mind independence, clarified by offering the following: "A statement that is true whether or not anyone believes or perceives them". But this doesn't address the issue I raised, it only pushes the question back a step further; what is truth, and how do we determine it?

Truth is just an assessment we make by comparing a proposition to it's subject. If they match, the proposition is true. If they do not match then the proposition is not true.

The subject can fall into one of two categories: internal or external. Internal would be it's own definition, i.e. all triangles have 3 sides. External would be comparing it to the external world, aka reality itself, i.e. all men are mortal.

So when Pro claims something is true, which one is he comparing the proposition to? If internal, then he's asserting nothing more than a definition, which is to say he's challenging me to refute a taugtology. If external, then Pro must show us where in the external world these truths manifest. 

Pro argues that my point here begs the question, asking "Why must objectivity be tied to empiricalreality?". The answer lies within the context of what we're debating. Pro claims these moral facts are metaphysical, but we are not. We are physical beings confined to a physical universe, so if Pro is arguing that moral facts, do not have any manifestation within this universe he cannot rationally assert them as an explanation for anything within it, which includes moral actions. 

Again, the resolution is that God best explains morality, yet what Pro is asserting has no explanatory power at all because these moral facts Pro claims to exist are indistinguishable from their own absence.

Epistemology  vs Ontology

Pro argues that I am appealing to a lack of consensus to assert morality's subjectivity. Nothing about my argument resembles this. My point is that standards, regardless of what we're talking about, are ultimately chosen, which makes them definitionally subjective. So if we don't decide what the standard of morality is, who does? 

Pro essentially argues - no one, it just is. That isn't an argument, it's just Pro's position in this debate dressed up as one.

In regards to that last point, Pro having begun with God (or rather his conception of God's nature) derives his moral ought from what he believes to be consistent with his nature. The question at the heart of this debate is; why should anyone else? Can Pro provide that answer without appealing to his own opinion or by merely asserting his position as correct? He has yet to do so.

Conflating Moral Ontology with Defining Morality / Conflating Moral Ontology with Divine Volition

Pro asserts that my position avoids the central claim that God's nature is what grounds objective truths, and remarkably also states "God does not write the rules of morality, they are based on his perfect, immutable, and necessary nature". But this is just begging the question.

By claiming morality is based on God's "perfect" nature Pro is again asserting the very claim he is supposed to be proving. On what basis has Pro evaluated God's nature to determine it is perfect? Based on his arguments so far, his nature is perfect because it matches precisely to his nature. In other words, this is nothing more than a taugtology, which is to say it's meaningless.

Pro has at least addressed one part of the dilemma; he tells us God does not write the rules of morality, thus morality is not subject to "whatever God says". This is clarifying. It tells us that God, the purported creator and ruler of the universe, under Pro's conception of him does not have the power determine what it's rules - as in the rules Pro's argument appeals to - are. 

So what then accounts for them? Pro asserts "God's nature" but all that does is kick the can back a step further without explaining anything. What accounts for God's nature, and what morally binds us to it? Pro has offered us nothing here but circularity. Again, if God cannot rewrite the rules of morality then he is subject to them just like everyone else and cannot therefore be their explanation.

Lastly, I never "dictated" as Pro suggests that anyone ought act with pure intentions. I explained the role that pure intentions play in any reasonable moral assessment. We're talking about logical consistency here, not adherence to some asserted cosmic force.

Moreover, if someone says, “We ought to act from pure intentions,” and this is framed as begging the question, then it should be asked: why is any moral “ought” not begging the question? The claim that “we ought to conform to God’s nature” is equally question begging unless that moral obligation can be independently justified.

Morality Explained

Pro asked that I expand on my views of what explains morality but didn't offer any critiques of my position so there's not much there to address. so to make my point I will focus on one contention Pro has relied on in this debate, the notion that there being nothing objectively wrong with torturing an infant for fun somehow qualifies as an argument in support of objective morality. But this argument is nothing more than an appeal to emotion.

The first problem is that Pro is conflating objectivity with morality, thereby implying that if something isn't objectively wrong, it's not wrong. This is not how it works. If morality is a product of moral values, those values are still held regardless of what they're ultimately based in. To claim such an act is not moral on the basis of a lack of objectivity is to disregard the concept of morality all together, which is exactly what Pro is doing here. But that disregard is a choice, not a logical extension.

The second and more relevant part to my point here is the appeal to emotion. This argument enforces within us the idea that our position on this - that it is wrong - is correct. And for it to be correct no matter what anyone thinks is appealing to all of us because it aligns with one of our most basic fundamental survival instincts ingrained within us through millions of years of evolution. In short, we value our own survival and our emotions are our key characteristic which allowed for our continuation. 

There is no cosmic protector required, the above is an illustration that easily explains it all.

Summary

Pro's case relies almost entirely on assuming what it needs to prove: that objective moral facts exist, that God’s nature grounds them, and that such grounding is meaningful and accessible.

It also mischaracterizes several critiques as “category errors” when those critiques are not based on definitional confusion but on philosophical disagreement. Ultimately, the question remains: what justifies moral objectivity without begging the question, and can the appeal to God truly resolve it without falling into circularity?

Until that’s answered convincingly, the claim that “God best explains morality” remains an assertion, not a demonstrated conclusion. Meanwhile I have provided an moral framework that matches to the human experience and shows why we hold certain moral values without a God required and Pro hasn't yet addressed. The resolution therefore fails.


Round 3
Pro
#5
Sorry I have been extremely busy with work and the new website project. I am going to have to waive this round. 
Not published yet
Round 4
Not published yet
Not published yet