Instigator / Pro
18
1485
rating
93
debates
46.24%
won
Topic
#6223

Resolved: The modal ontological argument is sound

Status
Finished

The debate is finished. The distribution of the voting points and the winner are presented below.

Winner & statistics
Better arguments
6
3
Better sources
6
4
Better legibility
3
3
Better conduct
3
3

After 3 votes and with 5 points ahead, the winner is...

David
Parameters
Publication date
Last updated date
Type
Standard
Number of rounds
4
Time for argument
One week
Max argument characters
10,000
Voting period
One month
Point system
Multiple criterions
Voting system
Open
Contender / Con
13
1579
rating
37
debates
68.92%
won
Description

INTRO

The modal ontological argument is an intriguing argument for the existence of God. Originally attributed to St. Anselm of Canterbury, Alvin Plantinga turned this argument into a modal argument for God's existence.

1. It is possible that a maximally great being exists.
2. If it is possible that a maximally great being exists, then a maximally great being exists in some possible world.
3. If a maximally great being exists in some possible world, then it exists in every possible world.
4. If a maximally great being exists in every possible world, then it exists in the actual world.
5. If a maximally great being exists in the actual world, then a maximally great being exists.
6. Therefore, a maximally great being exists.

=== Definitions ==

Ontological argument: See above

Sound: An argument is sound if and only if it is valid and all its premises are true. If an argument is sound, then the conclusion follows

-- STRUCTURE --

1. Opening
2. Rebuttals
3. Rebuttals
4. Rebuttals/Close

Rules

1. No forfeits
2. Citations must be provided in the text of the debate
3. No new arguments in the final speeches
4. Observe good sportsmanship and maintain a civil and decorous atmosphere
5. No trolling
6. No "kritiks" of the topic (challenging assumptions in the resolution)
7. For all resolutional terms, individuals should use commonplace understandings that fit within the logical context of the resolution and this debate
8. The BOP is on Pro; Con's BOP lies in proving Pro wrong. Con may make original arguments if he wants to.
9. Rebuttals of new points raised in an adversary's immediately preceding speech may be permissible at the judges' discretion even in the final round (debaters may debate their appropriateness)
11. Violation of any of these rules merits a loss.

Criterion
Pro
Tie
Con
Points
Better arguments
3 point(s)
Better sources
2 point(s)
Better legibility
1 point(s)
Better conduct
1 point(s)
Reason:

This, as expected, turned out to be a milestone debate. The sense of the challenge requires a good grounding in the philosophy of modal logic
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-modal/,
and first in that grounding is understanding the language, and by language, the meaning of, for example, ◊□P → □P.  Well, that's not common English, is it? Regardless, anyone sufficiently interested should read the entire section of "Modal logic" in the site given above. Read and re-read until understanding is reached. or you're in Con's position: "That's what I spent the whole debate trying to understand, and you [sic] guess is still as good as mine" [Comments, Con post #20. I do not render this quote as part of my RFD, but merely as exemplary of Con's self-admitted misunderstanding.] If anyone is interested in the more complete edition of my RFD, I have it and will provide it. [that may take a bit as I am taking off next week for surgery.]

fauxlaw RFD:
Argument: This would be a very lengthy RFD, so I'll cut to the chase in Pro's R4 which summarizes the Pro arguments of R1, R2, R3: "My opponent has conceded every premise except for premise 3 [I have confirmed this is the case]. Unfortunately my opponent continues to misunderstand premise 3 and misunderstand modal logic. This is not a logical contradiction but an axiom of modal logic: ◊□P → □P.  ◊□P means there exists at least one possible world where P is true in all possible worlds (i.e., P is necessarily true in that world). In other words, if P can be necessarily true somewhere, its necessity holds universally. Thus we are saying because there is at least one possible world where God is necessary, then God is necessary in all possible worlds. This is not a stretch but a basic foundational axiom of modal logic. In modal logic, necessary means true in all possible worlds, including the actual world as the actual world is a possible world."

Con's rebuttal: "I don't quite understand what my opponent means by "If God being "possible" necessitates him being real then he is no longer possible, because something that is possible cannot be 100% real, there must be a chance that it isn't real." By definition anything that is real in the actual world is possible. The word "possible" is a maybe-word, not a definite-word."

Con's rebuttal is out of a common dictionary [though Con never cites one as a source, which Is not the Stanford Dictionary of Philosophy; Pro's source, and, therefore, the more credible source. Pro wins this debate argument going away.

Sources: Pro's sources are so credible, even Con uses them, but draws the wrong conclusions from them, and, otherwise, offers no self-supporting sourcing. Pro wins the source points.

Legibility: one might draw the conclusion that Con's misunderstanding of Pro's modal logic yields a legibility loss, but legibility is not descriptive of misunderstanding. What Con writes is certainly legible, it's just not meeting modal logic
Pro, by contrast, while arguing points normally beyond the level of even a college degree not rooted in modal logic, and therefore are not understood well, his argument is legible. Tie

Conduct: Both participants conducted themselves well. Tie.

Criterion
Pro
Tie
Con
Points
Better arguments
3 point(s)
Better sources
2 point(s)
Better legibility
1 point(s)
Better conduct
1 point(s)
Reason:

A hearty well done to both Pro and Con for this debate.

Firstly, regarding sources I will be giving a tie. While Pro gave the sources, it seems to me that Con was challanging the acedemia of the source and as such, I at least virtually consider Con to be using the same source.

I had very little difficulty in understanding the legibility of both Pro and Con.

Both had very good conduct.

Regarding the arguments: I believe pro best stated his argument in R4 with: "Thus we are saying because there is at least one possible world where God is necessary, then God is necessary in all possible worlds. This is not a stretch but a basic foundational axiom of modal logic. In modal logic, necessary means true in all possible worlds, including the actual world as the actual world is a possible world."

Which Con refuted with in R3 actually: "Using meer logic we can't make a possible being necessary, because as a quality of being possible, it must be possible that it does not exist. " and "By possible, I mean that something could exist, or it could not. That doesn't necessitate the possible thing existing."

My vote goes to Con because, essentially, the word "necessary" in modal logic must be taken under the context/mode of the "can be." Meaning we are speaking of what would be necessary in a "can be" context, as is shown in the way this argument is layed out.

According to the definition of the word possible from modal logic: it signifies that a proposition can be true in at least one possible world, or that a state of affairs can be realized without contradiction.

And as Pro pointed out "neccessary means true in all possible worlds, including the actual world which is a possible world." which shows that Pro has removed the context of the "can be" that is demanded by defintion of possible in the same sentence, which Con refuted with: " Using meer logic we can't make a possible being necessary, because as a quality of being possible, it must be possible that it does not exist." Showing that Pro changed the context in his argument.

For those who have studied Formal Logic, Pro changed the suppositio of the word: necessary. He went from ideal (a necessary thing in this "can be" context) to real (a necessary thing in a "is" context) in a syllogism, which is a fallacy as Con showed by bringing in real being for the suppositio of the word: necessary.

Criterion
Pro
Tie
Con
Points
Better arguments
3 point(s)
Better sources
2 point(s)
Better legibility
1 point(s)
Better conduct
1 point(s)
Reason:

My 3rd attempt to vote on a debate topic which is pretty clear to be misunderstood by con but he keeps reporting my vote because he might have the illusion that he won this.
Reason: Pro starts by explaining the modal ontological argument. step by step. And also adresses common objections.

Con: Starts by suggesting that he might not understand a part of the MOA.
"This is a premise I have a problem with, but that may be just because I don't understand your wording of it completely. Currently in this syllogism, we've only established that God exists in the world of thought, or hypothetical worlds. However this means that God isn't actually real, and it's actually God. You've established that God must exist in the real world in order to be God, but that implies that a "God" existing in thought simply isn't God rather than necessitating God's existence. "

Then again continues with a false analogy and battles with the wording of the MOA:
"Also, this premise rests on the assumption that the universe is infinite. If you have an infinite amount of monkeys on typewriters or an infinite amount of time, then yes, they will eventually produce the works of Shakespeare. However you haven't proven that the universe is infinite in either time or space. In a set of infinite numbers, the number 12 is a necessary being, but in a set of the numbers 1-5 it is an impossible being. Likewise with the universe, the possibility of God doesn't directly translate to his existence in any possible worlds."

When it is clear that no one in this debate claims for an infinite universe but rather 'infinite possible universes'.

After having made a long, weak argument and having suggested multiple times that he does not understand the topic, he closes with a premise of the MOA saying it gets us nowhere, without countering it with a logical argument:
"The whole syllogism is essentially saying "If God exists, then God must exist" which is tautologically true, and gets us nowhere."

Then again suggests himself that he is not understanding the argument:
"This is the part you didn't explain very well, and I still don't quite understand. God is logically coherent, but that doesn't necessitate his existence. The Padres winning the world series is logically coherent but as a long suffering fan, I can tell you that it hasn't happened. "

Starts his next argument quite well for a brief moment: "A possible thing cannot go from possible to existence without removing the fog of ignorance. Using meer logic we can't make a possible being necessary, because as a quality of being possible, it must be possible that it does not exist."

Then in the end he is once more blessed by the bliss of ignorance: "The problem is that P being possible does not necessitate it existing in at least one world. We've been over this, if P is "possibly real" then by definition it must also be "possibly unreal", otherwise it automatically becomes necessary. There does not have to be a world where P exists, because as you stated, P is "possible". That means that it's also a possibility that P exists in no worlds. Since P is possible, it cannot then be necessary. If something is necessary, then there is 100% chance it exists, but if it is possible, then the possibility of existence must be less than 100%. Possibility of existence cannot equal 100 and a non-100 number at the same time. "

Showing clearly that he has misunderstood the modal possibility.

The reason why this is not a tie: This debate centers on the MOA being sound. Pro presents it, clearly. Adresses common objections. Explains the modal possibility logic multiple times to con. He has provided the arguments on why the MOA is indeed sound.
Con has the duty to show that it is not. Unfortunately he cannot do so because he is stuck to trying to understand the topic throughout the debate and not countering.